Ontology and Arbitrariness David Builes Forthcoming in the Australasian Journal of Philosophy Abstract In many different ontological debates, anti-arbitrariness considerations push one towards two opposing extremes. For example, in debates about mereology, one may be pushed towards a maximal ontology (mereological universalism) or a minimal ontology (mereological nihilism), because any intermediate view seems objectionably arbitrary. However, it is usually thought that antiarbitrariness considerations on their own cannot decide between these maximal or minimal views. I will argue that this is a mistake. Anti-arbitrariness arguments may be used to motivate a certain popular thesis in the philosophy of mathematics that rules out the maximalist view in many different ontological debates. 1. Introduction Many philosophers have wanted to avoid an ontology that is arbitrary. We shouldn’t think that simples-arranged-table-wise form a fusion, but simples-arranged-chair-wise do not. We shouldn’t think that the property of being a fork exists, but the property of being a knife does not. We shouldn’t think that the proposition that grass is green exists, but the proposition that snow is white does not. Metaphysicians shouldn’t be in the business of drawing these kinds of completely arbitrary ontological lines. Unfortunately, considerations of arbitrariness only seem to take us so far. They only push us towards opposite extremes. On one extreme, there is a maximalist view, according to which ‘all possible’ objects of a certain kind exist. On the other extreme, there is a minimalist view, according to which no objects of the relevant kind exist. Any intermediate view must draw some kind of ontological line, and it is easy to worry that any such line (even a vague one) would be unacceptably arbitrary. However, even if one rules out intermediate views on arbitrariness grounds, one is still left with deciding between maximalist views and minimalist views. At this point, it seems like one must appeal to additional theoretical desiderata to decide the issue, and so philosophers who are otherwise united in their desire to have a non-arbitrary ontology must part ways. 2 It would nice if this wasn’t so. It would be nice if anti-arbitrariness reasoning could go further, by helping us decide between these two opposite extremes. Then, philosophers who are united in their desire to avoid arbitrariness need not part ways. Anti-arbitrariness considerations alone could resolve the relevant ontological debates. My goal is to argue that this can be done. In particular, I will argue that there is a certain position in the philosophy of mathematics, which itself is primarily motivated on the basis of anti-arbitrariness concerns, that decides many of these ontological debates in favor of the minimalist. Of course, some philosophers might have independent reasons to avoid this position in the philosophy of mathematics. However, my main goal is to show that an argument for minimalism over maximalism can be given, purely on the grounds of anti-arbitrariness. 2. Indefinite Extensibility and Arbitrariness In order to avoid intolerable arbitrariness, many philosophers of mathematics have been attracted to the claim that certain kinds of entities are indefinitely extensible. There are many different ways to understand the thesis of indefinite extensibilty.1 For our purposes, we will be focusing on a modal version of the thesis, defended by Linnebo (2010, 2013). Consider the question of which pluralities of objects can form a set. Linnebo has argued that, necessarily, any things whatsoever can form a set: Set Indefinite Extensibility (SIE): ☐∀xx♢∃y(Set(y) ˄ ∀x(x ≺ xx ↔️ x ∈ y)) Before we turn to defending this principle, an immediate question arises as to how one should interpret the modal operators in SIE. After all, on a standard view, according to which the ontology of mathematics is metaphysically necessary, interpreting the modal operators as expressing metaphysical necessity would collapse SIE into its paradoxical non-modal analogue. However, there are a number of ways of interpreting these modal operators that sidestep this issue. Linnebo (2010, 2013) himself interprets the modal operators as involving a primitive kind of set-theoretic modality, according to which there could be more sets than there actually are. Field (1993) endorses a notion of ‘conceptual possibility’, according to which it is conceptually contingent which mathematical objects there are. Russell (1919) endorses a notion of ‘logical 1For some different accounts of indefinite extensibiliy, see Uzquiano (2015). For some defenses of the indefinite extensibility of sets, broadly interpreted, see Russell (1906), Dummett (1991), Rayo and Uzquiano (2006), Linnebo (2010, 2013), Levey (2016), and Warren (2017). Some understandings of indefinite extensibility crucially assume that one cannot quantify over absolutely everything that exists. However, the modalized version that we will be considering does not have this presupposition. The thesis that one may quantify over absolutely everything that exists is a popular one among contemporary metaphysicians engaged in the debates that we will be considering below. For example, Lewis (1991: 68), Sider (2003: xx-xxiv), van Inwagen (2002), and Williamson (2003) have all defended the possibility of unrestricted quantification. Following these metaphysicians, I will be assuming the orthodox view that quantifying unrestrictedly is unproblematic. 3 possibility’, according to which facts about ontology are never logically necessary. We may also interpret the relevant notion of possibility as a kind of idealized conceivability, defended by Chalmers (2002). Lastly, there are a number of contemporary philosophers who have argued that, even if the ontology of mathematics is ‘metaphysically’ necessary, there is a (perhaps more interesting) broader notion of real possibility according to which the ontology of mathematics is contingent.2 In any case, when we are engaged in the business of deciding between rival metaphysical positions regarding mathematical ontology (or mereology, or many other metaphysical disputes) there is certainly some sense in which we may intelligibly and coherently entertain different metaphysical hypotheses, even if these rival metaphysical hypotheses do not turn out to be genuine metaphysical possibilities. In what follows, you may interpret the modal operators of SIE in whatever way you wish to precisify this intuitive idea, but I will be using the terms ‘logically possible’ and ‘conceivable’ more or less interchangeably. Back to SIE: why believe it? SIE is attractive because it gives a principled, non-arbitrary answer to the question of which objects can coherently form sets: any objects whatsoever. Moreover, SIE is entirely immune to the set-theoretic paradoxes. SIE in no way clashes with the purely mathematical fact that there is no set of all sets. The existence of such a set would directly contradict the axiom of regularity, since the set of all sets would have to contain itself. However, this mathematical fact is entirely irrelevant to the claim that for any things, it is logically possible or conceivable that they form a set. When one is conceiving of a set that contains all of the actually existing sets, one is conceiving of a set that is in no way intrinsically paradoxical (for example, it does not contain itself). Anyone who denies SIE faces an explanatory challenge. How could there be some things such that it is logically impossible or inconceivable that they form a set? Just as intermediate views in mereology must draw a line between those pluralities that form fusions and those that do not, deniers of SIE must draw a line between those pluralities that can coherently form sets and those that cannot. Prima facie, however, it seems that for any things, it is easily conceivable that they form a set. After all, a set is completely characterized by its members, so specifying some plurality of objects seems to completely characterize some corresponding set. Deniers of SIE need to provide an explanation for why it is logically impossible for certain pluralities to form a corresponding set, otherwise their position is objectionably arbitrary. According to defenders of indefinite extensibility, this explanatory challenge has not been met. Perhaps the most common response to this challenge among deniers of SIE is that some pluralities are ‘too big’ to form sets (see Lewis (1991) and Burgess (2004)). It is then often claimed that what it is to be ‘too big’ is to be equinumerous with the plurality of all ordinals oo that actually exist. Linnebo (2010: 153-154) has argued that this common view does not meet the explanatory challenge as follows: 2See, for example, Rosen (2006) and Clarke-Doane (2019, forthcoming). Balaguer (1998: 44) also argues for a similar conclusion in saying that ‘it is doubtful that our mathematical theories are necessary in any interesting sense’. 4 Consider the question why there are not more ordinals than oo. For instance, why cannot the plurality oo form a set, which would then be an additional ordinal, larger than any member of oo? According to the view under discussion, the explanation is that oo are too many to form a set, where being too many is defined as being as many as oo. So the proposed explanation moves in a tiny circle. The threshold cardinality is what it is because of the cardinality of the plurality of all ordinals; but the cardinality of this plurality is what it is because of the threshold. I conclude that the response fails to make any substantial progress, and that the proposed threshold remains arbitrary. In the absence of a compelling answer to this explanatory challenge, those metaphysicians who wish to avoid arbitrariness ought to endorse SIE. From SIE, it is easy to derive the following claim, which will prove to be important for many of the arguments below: Cardinal Indefinite Extensibility (CIE): ☐∀xx(∀x(x≺xx → Cardinal(x)) → ♢∃y(Cardinal(y) ˄ ∀x(x ≺ xx → y > x))3 In words, CIE is the claim that, necessarily, for any cardinals (those sets which correspond to the different sizes of infinity), there could be a larger cardinal. In order to prove CIE from SIE, let the xx be any plurality of cardinals. Either there is a largest cardinal in the xx or there isn’t. If there is, call it κ. It is a consequence of the standard ZFC axioms in set theory that for every cardinal κ, there exists a strictly larger cardinal. So, the standard ZFC axioms themselves guarantee the existence of a larger cardinal than each of the xx. Next, suppose there is no largest cardinal in the xx. Then, by SIE, there could be a set whose only elements are everything that is an element of one of the xx. The set would just be the union of the cardinals in xx, so (since every union of cardinals is itself a cardinal) it would itself be a cardinal greater than all of the cardinals in the xx, as desired. With SIE and CIE in hand, we are ready to argue for minimalist views over maximalist views in a variety of ontological debates. 3. Mathematical Objects Which abstract mathematical objects, if any, exist? According to a minimalist view, there are no mathematical objects. According to intermediate views, some (logically) possible mathematical objects exist, and others do not. Perhaps, for example, the real numbers exist, but the complex numbers do not. Or perhaps differentiable manifolds exist, but rings do not. Or perhaps countable sets exist, but uncountable sets do not. Mark Balaguer (1995, 1998) and Linksy and Zalta (1995, 2006) have argued in favor of a maximalist view of mathematical ontology. According to Balaguer, ‘the ordinary, actually existing mathematical objects exhaust 3The relevant notion of ‘>’ here is that y > x iff y is strictly larger in cardinality than x. 5 all of the logical possibilities for such objects; that is, that there actually exist mathematical objects of all logically possible kinds; that is, that all the mathematical objects that logically possibly could exist actually do exist; that is, that the mathematical realm is plenitudinous’ (1998: 6).4 Anti-arbitrariness concerns push one towards maximalist or minimalist views. Just as it seems arbitrary to draw a line between those material objects that form fusions and those that do not, it seems arbitrary to draw a line between those possible mathematical structures that exist and those that do not. However, the relevant maximalist view is inconsistent with SIE. If there is a plenitude of all possible mathematical objects, then there is a plenitude of all possible pure sets. Informally, there is a plenitude of pure sets just in case there couldn’t be more pure sets than there actually are. We may formalize this as follows: Set Plenitude: ∃xx(∀x(x ≺ xx → Set(x)) ˄ ~♢∃y(Set(y) ˄ ∀x(x ≺ xx → y ≠ x)) After all, if there could be a further pure set, then it should actually exist if maximalism is true. We can now present our argument against maximalism as follows: 1. If maximalism is true, Set Plenitude is true. 2. SIE is true. 3. If SIE is true, Set Plenitude is false. 4. Therefore, maximalism is false. The argument is clearly valid. I have already argued in favor of premises 1 and 2. It is easy to see that premise 3 is true. Take the plurality of all pure sets ss that there are. According to SIE there could be a distinct pure set, namely one whose members are exactly the ss. This contradicts Set Plenitude. The intuitive idea behind this style of argument is straightforward. The maximalist tries to have all of the mathematical objects that there could possibly be. However, according to SIE, there is no sense to be made of ‘all of the mathematical objects that there could possibly be’. No matter how many mathematical objects there are, there could always be more. It is simply an 4It is important to note that these kinds of modal characterizations of maximalist views, according to which ‘all possible objects of kind K exist’, should also not be interpreted as involving metaphysical modality, because the standard view that the ontological commitments of metaphysics are metaphysically necessary renders them vacuous. Rather, these modal formulations of maximalist views should use some kind of logical or conceptual possibility, as Balaguer uses. The interpretation of the modal operators in ‘Set Plenitude’ below should therefore be interpreted in the same way as the modal operators in SIE. Otherwise, the argument I present below, regarding Set Plenitude and SIE, would rest on an equivocation between modal operators and fail to be valid. Similar considerations will apply in future sections, regarding maximalist views where ‘all possible’ possible worlds exist, or ‘all possible’ properties exist, etc. 6 illusion that there is a coherent minimalist position and a coherent maximalist position. There is only a coherent minimalist position. Therefore, considerations of anti-arbitrariness should push us towards holding a minimalist position. 4. Other Abstract Objects The same style of argument can be generalized to a wide range of controversial abstract objects. In each case, the maximalist tries to have ‘all possible’ abstract objects of a certain kind, but such a position is ultimately illusory. No matter how many abstract objects of that kind that there might be, there could always have been more. Consider, for example, the case of propositions. Are there any? Minimalists say there are no propositions. However, if one does believe in the existence of propositions, one shouldn’t just believe in three or four of them. Instead, one should endorse a maximalist view according to which there is a plenitude of propositions. In particular, one should at least endorse the following: Proposition Plenitude: If it is possible that there be some cardinal number κ, then there is the proposition that there are exactly κ-many angels.5 After all, if there were some upper limit to the number of angels that propositions could describe, then such an upper limit would be wholly arbitrary. Unfortunately, CIE and Proposition Plenitude imply a contradiction. Let any proposition of the form there are exactly κ-many angels be denoted by ‘Pκ’. Let pp the plurality of all such propositions. By CIE, there could be some cardinal λ strictly greater than every cardinal κ such that there is some proposition of the form Pκ in pp. By Proposition Plenitude, there exists a proposition of the form Pλ. However, such a proposition is not one of the pp, even though the pp is supposed to include every proposition of the form Pκ for some κ. We have reached a contradiction. Let us turn to another example. Are there any properties? Here, we need to draw an important distinction. Following Lewis (1983) and many others, we should distinguish between an abundant and a sparse conception of properties. According to a sparse conception of properties, only certain highly or perfectly natural properties exist, perhaps those given in fundamental physics. According to an abundant conception, properties may be as disjunctive or gerrymandered as one likes. There is no argument against the existence of a sparse collection of perfectly natural properties from indefinite extensibility considerations, since there is no good reason for believing in a corresponding pair of plenitude and indefinitely extensibility claims for such properties. 5The use of ‘angels’ here (and throughout) is inessential. One may instead consider the proposition that there is a κ-dimensional space-time or the proposition that there are κ-many island universes. 7 However, are there any abundant properties? The minimalist says no. The maximalist, on the other hand, should endorse the following principle: Property Plenitude: If it is possible that there be some cardinal number κ, then there is the property of being in a world with at most κ angels. However, Property Plenitude falls into contradiction with CIE for the same reasons that Proposition Plenitude falls into contradiction with CIE. Let us go through one last example. Are there any possibilia? For example, is there anything that is my possible twin? Minimalists say no. Maximalists, in the form of Necessitism, say yes. Necessitism, defended by Williamson (2013), Goodman (2016) and others, is the view that necessarily, everything is necessarily something.
Leave a Reply